Desire paths, or, brief thoughts on guideline judgments prompted by Setu v R [2017] NZHC 1839

desire_path
Pictured: R v Taueki (left) and grievous bodily harm sentencing in practice (right)

Desire paths

Local authorities install footpaths in parks, and then find that nobody uses them.  Instead, shortcut paths are worn into the grass nearby, indicating where people are actually walking.  They are called desire paths.

The Court of Appeal issues guideline judgments for sentencing decisions.  They are the paths that counsel and the lower courts are expected to walk when determining starting points in sentencing.

The recent sentencing appeal decision of Setu v R [2017] NZHC 1839 exposed a desire path: a seam of cases all of which were at odds with the numerical guidance in a Court of Appeal guideline judgment.  The High Court rejected the appeal and confirmed the primacy of the guideline judgment.

The result is unsurprising (it is a brave High Court judge that would put to one side a Court of Appeal guideline judgment).  But I think it raises interesting questions about the validity (in a lay sense) of the Court of Appeal’s guideline judgments.  If significant numbers of sentencing decisions are low-balling starting points despite a guideline judgment saying they should be higher, then either we need a new guideline that rejigs the numbers in line with actual practice, or we need a grumpy reminder from the Court of Appeal that sentencing judges need to get with the programme.

In Setu we got something approaching the latter (albeit from the High Court), but I’m not sure it’s enough.

Guideline judgments

(Skip this part if you know what guideline judgments are.)

The Court of Appeal has set guideline judgments for certain types of offences (R v Mako for aggravated robbery, R v Terewi for cannabis offending, R v Fatu for drug offending, R v AM for sexual offending).

The purpose of these decisions is to shortcut sentencing decisions.  They offer guides for quantifying sentences based on either examples of types of offending, or the presence of certain features of the offending.

For example, the guideline judgment for grievous bodily harm offending is R v Taueki [2005] 3 NZLR 372, (2005) 21 CRNZ 769 (CA).  The Court listed a range of factors at paragraph [31]: things like the use of extreme violence, premeditation, serious injury, the use of weapons, attacking the head, and more.

Then, the Court set out bands containing a range of starting points:

  1. Band one: 3-6 years’ imprisonment.
  2. Band two: 5-10 years’ imprisonment.
  3. Band three: 9-14 years’ imprisonment.

The Court then said that where a certain number of the paragraph [31] factors are present, an offence will fall into a certain band.

Finally, the Court emphasised that the bands should be “used flexibly”, and that “the features of the offending in each case must be carefully assessed in order to establish a starting point which properly reflects the culpability inherent in the offending” (at [42]).

If these guideline judgments didn’t exist, then you would have to find comparator cases in each sentencing decision and, on each occasion, have to analogise a wide range of cases to the particular facts of the instant case.  Guideline judgments are intended to bring broad consistency to sentencing decisions.

Setu v R [2017] NZHC 1839

Mr Setu had been sentenced to a total of five years’ imprisonment for a small number of charges, with a lead offence of wounding with intent to cause grievous bodily harm (Crimes Act 1961, s 188(1).  Maximum sentence 14 years’ imprisonment).  The sentencing judge used the guidance in R v Taueki to place Mr Setu’s offending in the lower end of band three, and took a starting point of 10 years’ imprisonment.

On appeal to the High Court, Mr Setu contended that the starting point was too high because:

  • the aggravating features had been double-counted; and
  • the starting point was higher than comparable (and more serious) cases.

Justice Mander dismissed the double counting ground and I do not intend to address it.

On the comparable starting point ground, Mr Setu’s counsel pointed to eight comparable decisions all of which, it was submitted, supported a starting point for Mr Setu of no more than eight years’ imprisonment.

Mr Setu’s starting point was therefore:

  • in step with the guidance in R v Taueki; but
  • out of step with the cases that had applied R v Taueki.

What to do?  The answer was a doubling down on R v Taueki.  The key paragraphs of Mander J’s decision on this point are below:

[46] Judge Neave was aware in taking a starting point of 10 years that there were sentencing decisions, indeed a majority of cases, where a lesser starting point has been applied. He noted the tension between those cases and the direct application of the Court of Appeal’s Taueki guidance, based upon the presence of identified aggravating features to which Mr Setu’s offending gives rise. A sentencing Judge is entitled to return to first principles and, in particular, to apply the guidance provided by the Court of Appeal when setting a starting point. This is particularly so when over the years since the 2005 Taueki decision, a body of decisions have accumulated which illustrate some variation in sentencing levels and perhaps to some extent “sentence drift” from the original guidance provided by the Court of Appeal.

[47] That development of itself may simply reflect what the Court of Appeal acknowledged in its Taueki decision, namely that sentencing ultimately involves the exercise of discretion and must allow for flexibility. The fact that some sentencing Courts have chosen, as they are entitled, to apply Taueki in a particular way does not, in my view, render another sentencing Court’s application of the Taueki guidance in another case inappropriate, so long as the starting point arrived at can be reconciled with the range the Court of Appeal has held to be available because of the nature and combination of aggravating features.

[48] To suggest otherwise would effectively relegate Taueki to a secondary source of guidance in favour of a requirement that a sentencing Court undertake a comprehensive review of cases, the circumstances of which will almost inevitably vary, before it may confidently impose a sentence for GBH offending. While assistance from other sentencing decisions provides a useful check, such an approach would largely defeat the purpose and utility of the guideline authority.

This is interesting for a number of reasons.

It has implications for sentencing appeals from offending where there is a guideline judgment.  It emphasises the primacy of the guideline judgment as the ultimate arbiter of sentence length on appeal, as well as at initial sentence.  The test for an excessive sentence should be by reference to the guideline, not by reference to comparable cases.   That last sentence is a little over-simplistic as one will still need to check that the aggravating features have been applied correctly (and not, for example, double-counted).

His Honour Mander J did not engage in any substantive way with the eight decisions counsel cited in order to try to distinguish them.  Rather, their inconsistency with Mr Setu’s starting point was plainly acknowledged.

I am not sure where that leaves the eight cases that counsel cited.  His Honour described them as “applying Taueki in a particular way” and that the judges in those cases were “entitled” to do so.  But under Mander J’s approach they are not the first port of call in determining whether a starting point is excessive (Taueki is).  They are not really the last port of call either, since Taueki will tell you all you need to know.  It’s a neat trick of overruling them without saying they’re wrong: “those decisions are fine, except you don’t need to look at them”.

Back to desire paths

One response to the issues that Setu raises would be to say that the sentencing levels as articulated by the Court of Appeal in Taueki are, on the whole, slightly too high for sentencing judges to stomach.  That is why there are so many cases similar to Mr Setu’s but with lower starting points.

In turn, that supports an argument that the local authority should heed the desire path, and the Court of Appeal should reconsider its guideline judgment in respect of the starting points it sets.  This would probably best be accomplished by changing the number of aggravating factors that need to be present to get to a particular band.  At the moment it is relatively low: you get to band two by having “two or three” aggravating features (Taueki at [38]).  This would have the effect of lowering the sentencing levels, without fiddling directly with the years of imprisonment (that’s important because you can’t just lower everything without shying away from the statutory maximum imposed by Parliament).

The alternative is a response along Mander J’s lines:  “no.  This is the guideline judgment.  It is not the appellate courts’ problems if the sentencing courts are lowballing the sentences sometimes.”  Or put another way “the desire path is not sanctioned.  Even if some people are walking it frequently it doesn’t mean it’s the right way.”

Constitutionally, that is no doubt correct.  It also exposes two problems.

First, four of the eight cases that counsel in Setu cited were Court of Appeal decisions confirming or altering the starting point imposed.  That means that even the Court of Appeal isn’t consistently applying its own guideline judgment.  I think that last sentence is mostly correct.  The Court would be reluctant to increase a sentence on appeal so I admit it’s perhaps not particularly fair, but it is correct to say that the Court of Appeal has been signing off decisions that do not necessarily conform to its guideline judgment.

Second and relatedly, it has exposed inconsistent sentencing practice which risks unfairness for prisoners.  Parity is jeopardised when a seam of generous sentencing is allowed to pass unchallenged, but comparatively sterner decisions are upheld.  An offender in Mr Setu’s position can perhaps feel hard done by that he does not receive a similar starting point in a range of cases that have all purported to apply the guideline judgment.

Sentencing is never going to be a precisely mathematical exercise.  All sentences will fall within a range.  What matters is that there is one path.  A wide path, perhaps, but one path all the same.  I think Setu v R shows there is some work to do.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s